John Cullinan, Bard College – Voting and Math
Is our current voting system the most fair?
John Cullinan, mathematician at Bard College, examines the arithmetic behind the way we vote.
John Cullinan is Associate Professor and Chair of the Mathematics Program at Bard College. His primary research focuses on the intersection of Number Theory and Representation Theory, and he has recently begun publishing in the Mathematics of Voting. Dr. Cullinan has been on the faculty at Bard College since 2006 after teaching for a year at Colby College. He received his Ph.D. from the University of Massachusetts Amherst in 2005.
Voting and Math
The simplest way for a group to choose between two options is by majority rules and this is perhaps the most widely-accepted manifestation of democracy. But there is something deeper to majority rules than is apparent at first. It is the only voting procedure that satisfies the following three properties at the same time:
- It is impossible to tell who voted for whom based on the winner;
- Both options have an equal chance of winning before voting begins; and
- If you want your candidate to win, you must vote for him or her.
In other words, the voting procedure to which we are intrinsically drawn is mathematically-provable to be the fairest voting procedure that exists.
However, when there are more than two options all bets are off. Instant runoff voting, plurality, and the Borda count are just a few examples of the many voting systems in place for deciding between three or more options, and each fails some measure of fairness. The area of mathematics known as Social Choice Theory provides a framework for studying the fairness of such voting systems.
What if your true preferences among the candidates include ties or indifference?
For example, I like chocolate better than vanilla. I like chocolate better than strawberry, but I have no preference between vanilla and strawberry. In this mock election, a traditional ranked ballot would require me to make a choice between vanilla and strawberry, meaning that I would be forced to submit a disingenuous ballot.
My collaborators and I recently completed a research project in Social Choice Theory where we developed a procedure that allows voters to submit ballots that reflect arbitrary preference rankings, including ties or indifference. In addition, we proved that ours is the only voting procedure for more than two candidates that satisfies all mathematical fairness axioms.
The choice between two options is clear. Adding additional choices presents a difficulty we’re aiming to improve upon.
Related Posts
-
Gale Sinatra, University of Southern California – If You Want Americans to Pay Attention to Climate Change, Just Call It Climate Change
Using complex jargon can lessen the impact of a message. Gale Sinatra, distinguished professor
-
Ian Afflerbach, University of North Georgia – How “Selling Out” Started with Political Corruption
We hear of people and rock bands being called sell outs. Where did this
Nice, but the article should have a link to Prof. Cullinan’s research. From the research page on his website, it appears that the research in question may’ve been published in his 2014 article about Borda counts for partial orderings, but I can’t tell for sure. I’ve gone ahead and downloaded the paper but it would be nice to know in advance if I’m looking at the right paper.